Difference between revisions of "Talk:CC Kant"
Nateoxford (talk | contribs) (New page: ==Summary of Groundwork draft== ===Background=== The ''Groundwork'' was written 1785. Kant meant it to be a popular work explaining his formulation of the moral law and how he believes f...) |
Nateoxford (talk | contribs) |
||
Line 9: | Line 9: | ||
<br>3. A proof of freedom. | <br>3. A proof of freedom. | ||
− | [[Contemporary Civilization|CC]] students are normally asked to read the first two parts. This is because Kant disowned the ''Groundwork'' version of the proof of freedom. Dissatisfied with it, he wrote a completely new proof of freedom in ''Critique of Practical Reason.'' Hence, modern scholars now consider the third part of the ''Groundwork'' philosophically irrelevant, and thus it is not included in the CC syllabus | + | [[Contemporary Civilization|CC]] students are normally asked to read the first two parts. This is because Kant disowned the ''Groundwork'' version of the proof of freedom. Dissatisfied with it, he wrote a completely new proof of freedom in ''Critique of Practical Reason.'' Hence, modern scholars now consider the third part of the ''Groundwork'' philosophically irrelevant, and thus it is not included in the CC syllabus. |
===Part 1=== | ===Part 1=== | ||
− | + | People are born with basic moral truths. So in merely presenting cases, one extracts moral knowledge. You don't need a philosopher to tell right from wrong - everybody understands morality just as much as everybody else does. | |
− | What Kant | + | What Kant regresses from ordinary moral understanding by providing a series of examples. From these cases you get a more explicit understanding of the implicit knowledge which you knew all along. In effect, he is extracting moral knowledge and hence giving the reader a more profound grasp of it. |
+ | |||
+ | Unsurprisingly, Kant concludes that the morality of an action lies in the intent. Further, Kant contends that the only good motive is duty. By "duty", he means doing what is right purely for the sake of doing what is right. In practice, this means sticking to our basic principles over more shallow and enticing choices. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Quick example: Suppose you hold the principle that stealing is bad. However, at a certain point you are overcome by the desire to steal something which you cannot afford by honest means. You are also a genius at criminal work, and the theft of the object would be a perfect crime; you would never be discovered or prosecuted for the theft. In this case, we have two normative forces opposing each other: on the one hand, your anti-stealing principle, and on the other, your desire for that object. Kant believes that rational human beings will recognize that the basic principle is superior to emotional impulses, and hence for most people the basic principle ought to win. You will decide to abstain from theft, not because you're afraid of the police or because you're afraid to ruin your reputation; you abstain ''simply because your principle says so.'' This is acting out of duty: a recognition of the fact that basic morality ought to be chosen merely because it is chosen. | ||
===Part II=== | ===Part II=== | ||
+ | The next rational step is to attempt to formulate a moral law. That's what Part II is about. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
===Part III=== | ===Part III=== |
Revision as of 01:34, 3 September 2010
Contents
Summary of Groundwork draft
Background
The Groundwork was written 1785. Kant meant it to be a popular work explaining his formulation of the moral law and how he believes freedom is possible. A more academic, technical, and complete version is found in Critique of Practical Reason, which was published in 1788.
The Groundwork is divided into three parts:
1. Refinement of moral knowledge via regression from ordinary moral understanding.
2. Using this moral knowledge to formulate the moral law (Kant will present three).
3. A proof of freedom.
CC students are normally asked to read the first two parts. This is because Kant disowned the Groundwork version of the proof of freedom. Dissatisfied with it, he wrote a completely new proof of freedom in Critique of Practical Reason. Hence, modern scholars now consider the third part of the Groundwork philosophically irrelevant, and thus it is not included in the CC syllabus.
Part 1
People are born with basic moral truths. So in merely presenting cases, one extracts moral knowledge. You don't need a philosopher to tell right from wrong - everybody understands morality just as much as everybody else does.
What Kant regresses from ordinary moral understanding by providing a series of examples. From these cases you get a more explicit understanding of the implicit knowledge which you knew all along. In effect, he is extracting moral knowledge and hence giving the reader a more profound grasp of it.
Unsurprisingly, Kant concludes that the morality of an action lies in the intent. Further, Kant contends that the only good motive is duty. By "duty", he means doing what is right purely for the sake of doing what is right. In practice, this means sticking to our basic principles over more shallow and enticing choices.
Quick example: Suppose you hold the principle that stealing is bad. However, at a certain point you are overcome by the desire to steal something which you cannot afford by honest means. You are also a genius at criminal work, and the theft of the object would be a perfect crime; you would never be discovered or prosecuted for the theft. In this case, we have two normative forces opposing each other: on the one hand, your anti-stealing principle, and on the other, your desire for that object. Kant believes that rational human beings will recognize that the basic principle is superior to emotional impulses, and hence for most people the basic principle ought to win. You will decide to abstain from theft, not because you're afraid of the police or because you're afraid to ruin your reputation; you abstain simply because your principle says so. This is acting out of duty: a recognition of the fact that basic morality ought to be chosen merely because it is chosen.
Part II
The next rational step is to attempt to formulate a moral law. That's what Part II is about.
Part III
Glossary
A priori: something is a priori only if it necessarily exists, only if it universally applies, and only if it arises from activity of the mind.
Maxim: a careful and deliberate principle of action. An example of a maxim is "I will not let anything interfere with my schoolwork." It is a principle which dictates further action.
More content and elucidation to follow. Nateoxford 07:40, 29 December 2009 (EST)